back to syllabus

Week 3 Lecture Notes

The Scientific Revolution and the Enlightenment

Part One:  The Scientific Revolution

 

New thinking about science (“natural philosophy”) slightly anticipated the rise of the new ideas in statecraft that were the focus of previous lectures  (Mercantilist, “politique” and Absolutist concepts).  And these new modes of scientific reasoning had an important influence on thinking about the power of kings and the State. 

But new ways of looking at science also influenced the social and political theorists of the Enlightenment, whose arguments would challenge and help to undermine the power claims of Europe’s Kings .

Coffin identifies 3 major changes associated with the Scientific Revolution of the 1500s and 1600s: 

1)      the shift to seeing the Sun (and not the Earth) as the center of the universe;

2)      the development of a mathematically-based physics to explain how this re-conceptualized universe works;

3)      and the working out of a “scientific method” that could be used both to describe and to predict the behavior of the natural world.

I would stress even more than Coffin that these developments helped shift the “center” of attention of European thought away from religion:  the Earth was pushed from the center of Universe, and with it, God was pushed from the center of thinking about nature. 

That is not the same thing as saying that the scientific revolution was “atheistic,” nor even principally “secular”—Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, Newton and other major figures in the new science were deeply religious people who believed that they were describing God’s grand plan. 

But by exposing the workings of nature as following rules—“laws”—that people can figure out and understand, the new science helped to re-imagine God as (to use Newton’s metaphor) a great clock maker, who made the clock (the universe) so that it would work according to certain rules, then set the clock running and stood back to watch it run.

Also, one of the principles of the new science was that understanding the laws that govern nature can help you understand how to manipulate and transform the natural world more effectively (here is the link between science and technology).

 

Two things to keep in mind:

A) The “big” steps in the scientific revolution did not “just happen”--it had roots; also, it did not happen all at once—it was a long, drawn out series of many accumulated discoveries and theories.

B) Scientific thinking did not (and has not) completely replaced magically thinking and other forms of non-scientific “reasoning.”

Again, we need to understand that the “scientific revolution” is related to ideas we have talked about already and ideas we will discuss next:

 

Link to mercantilism and absolutism:  Once the basic “method” of scientific thinking began to establish itself among the educated elite and wielders of power in Europe, it helped promote the “rationalist”  “reason of state” ideas that we discussed earlier. 

Link to the Enlightenment:  New science thinking also led to the idea that human society, like nature, followed laws that could be observed, defined, and explained.  Enlightenment thinkers, building from the scientific approach, concluded that if you can use knowledge of nature to improve on nature, then you could also use knowledge of mankind to improve society.

 

Background:  The scientific revolution did not “come out of nowhere”

In the 1700s Enlightenment thinkers had imagined the medieval world as steeped in ignorance (they thought that between the fall of Rome and the Renaissance the world had lost all of the culture of the ancient Romans and Greeks);  for a long time historians were influenced by this view, and treated the Scientific Revolution as a very sudden and dramatic break with all medieval thought. 

But in the late 20th century, historians “pushed back” the origins of scientific into the late middle ages, as far back as the 1100s, when Catholic clerics and artists both began giving attention to “rediscovered” classical texts and learning. 

According to medieval thinkers who combined Classical and Christian ideas, the universe was hierarchical (like the society of the era):  they often described it as a giant ladder from Hell, to Earth, to Heaven.  They believed that Earth stood motionless at the center of the universe; seven planets (counting the Moon and the Sun) revolved around the Earth in perfect circular orbits and at uniform speeds, each on its own crystal sphere; the stars moved around the Earth on an 8th crystal sphere;  a 9th Heavenly sphere lay beyond the stars; an outermost 10th sphere, the Empyrean, surrounded everything else and was the location of God and the angels. 

In this conception of nature, everything on Earth was made of 4 elements that constantly mixed together and changed:  earth, water, air, and fire; everything in the other, heavenly spheres was made of “ether”—a perfect, pure, incorruptible and unchanging element that could not be found on earth.  This conception of nature fit both with the ancient teachings of Aristotle and with the theology of the Church.

Early examples of “new” thinking:  As early as the 1300s, some European philosophers began to argue that there was a difference between the study of nature and the study of theology—that humans could not know the mind of God (although “reveled” truth and faith could bring man closer to God), but man could learn the laws that govern nature.

In the late 1300s and early 1400s, Renaissance scholars studying the Classical world helped to revive interest in the mathematical (especially geometric) works of the Egyptian Hermes and the Greeks Archimedes, Pythagoras and Ptolemy (who had used math to explain why the “odd” orbits of the planets did not behave as Aristotle had said they should). 

Along with this new interest in mathematics, Renaissance craftsmen began applying mathematics to new technologies, such as lens grinding (for optics), which made possible the new science of Astronomy. It was in the new study of Astronomy that science had its most significant early breakthroughs—although few of them had immediate impact. 

The Science that led the way:  new ideas about Astronomy in the 1500s and early 1600s: 

At the dawn of the 1500s, Nicholas Copernicus used mathematics to determine that the Sun was not a planet and that the Earth was a planet—and that the earth and the planets orbited around the Sun.  He did not publish his conclusions until the 1540s.  The implications of this idea, that the Earth revolved around the sun (which is where we get the word “Revolution”), were huge:  it implied that God had not put MAN at the center of the universe, either. 

In the three generations after Copernicus, other astronomers punched more holes in Aristotle’s universe, observing new stars (which meant that the heavens were  NOT unchanging), determining that planets orbited in ellipses (not perfect circles) each at its own speed (not at a fixed speed). 

Most famously, in the early 1600s Galileo Galilei combined the use of a telescope to collect new observational data with the use of mathematics to explain that data:  with these methods, he documented craters on the moon and other evidence that the heavens were not made of perfectly smooth, unchanging, un-corruptible ether; moons orbiting Jupiter, which further “de-throned” the Earth as the only center of the universe; his observations and calculations supported Copernicus—the earth moved around the sun and not visa versa.

Added together on top of previous new findings (of Copernicus, Brahe, and Keppler), Galileo’s claims constituted an attack at the very basis of the Catholic Church’s established Aristotle-based conception of nature.  As we all know, this brought Galileo into conflict with the Church, and he eventually “recanted.” 

But by combining observation (data gathering), the use of mathematics to develop a theory to explain the data, and experimentation to test his theories, Galileo had not only helped to shatter the old conjunction of “religious truth” and “science”—he had helped to create the modern Scientific Method. 

Science and Epistemology:  Bacon and Descartes 

What we call “Science” was understood in the Early Modern era to be a branch of Philosophy—natural philosophy.  But new scientific discoveries also led to much rethinking in the branch of Philosophy known as “Epistemology”—the study of how we know what we know.

Two major schools of thinking about the methods of Natural Philosophy (science) and Epistemology emerged in the 1600s.  One of these is generally associated with England, and is often called as “Empiricism” or inductive method; the other, which held more sway on the continent, is often called “Cartesian” or deductive method.

As Coffin explains, in the early 1600s English philosopher Sir Frances Bacon argued that humans learn of the world by collecting information through their senses (by observation).  They then use their intellect to draw logical conclusions to explain the “data” that they gather through observation. 

This is called “Empiricism” because it holds that uncovering truth requires the collection of “empirical” evidence (rather than pure reason or pure logic); the method of “lining up the physical facts” to reach a conclusion is called “induction” or inductive reasoning.

Bacon and his followers argued that such a method would lead to the discovery of “useful” and “practical” knowledge that would help humans control and shape their environment. 

Bacon’s views were elaborated by a series of other British philosophers:  in regard to Epistemology, the most important was John Locke, who we most often think of as a political philosopher (e.g., his “contract theory” of government).  In 1690, in his “Essay on Human Understanding,” Locke argued that human beings are born “blank slates,” with no “innate” ideas; all we know, all we learn, is derived from experience, from the senses.  This view of knowledge, which was closely tied to an approach to answering scientific questions, would also prove extremely influential to new thinking about “social science.”

In contrast to the approach of Bacon and the Empiricists was the view of French philosopher René  Descartes, who also lived and wrote in the early 1600s.  Descartes argued that our understanding of the world came through application of  reason—pure logic.

In his essay “A Discourse on Method” (1637), Descartes argued that all ideas must be subjected to critical examination (instead of taking any idea as a “given”), that this examination must be based upon reason, and that it required establishing a “first principle”—a the thing that he could know with certainty—from which other arguments could be built.  Descartes’ first principle was that he himself existed.  As Descartes put it, “I think, therefore I am.” 

From that starting point, he argued, one could “reason outward” to determine other principles on the basis of pure logic and mathematics.  For Descartes, this meant that science could be freed from other philosophical concerns, such as morality:  instead, it would be the realm of things that can be calculated.  Descartes approach to problem solving is often described as “deductive reasoning.”

The difference between the Cartesian and Empiricist method can be put simply:

The Cartesians argued that truths could be established through mathematics/logical calculations, and that the observed world would behave in the ways described by the math—their aim was to find the logical laws that governed systems;

    The Baconians/Empiricists argued that you must begin with observations of reality (observational and experimental data), then use reason and math to describe and explain what had been observed—their aim was describing and explaining that which was observed.

 

A New Metaphor and a New Scientific Community

One of the many things that the Cartesians and the Empiricists had in common is that most used a new metaphor to describe nature:  the machine.

The metaphors that philosophers used to describe man, nature, and society previous to the scientific revolution tended to be hierarchical and  “organic”—society, for instance, was described in terms of patriarchal family relations (the state as a family), and the universe was described in a similar fashion.

In the mid-to-late 1600s, the metaphor became the machine—each element of nature, according to many “natural philosophers” could be understood as a machine with particular functions, and all these machines behaved according to (followed) the same fundamental laws of nature.  Descartes, for instance, saw humans as “machines with reason.”  Robert Hooke described the orbits of the planets as “machine like.”  William Harvey’s discovery of the circulation of blood, for instance, was based upon the idea that the heart works like a machine—a pump.

According to the most important scientist of the period, Isaac Newton, described God as a great and mysterious machine builder, who for reasons beyond the grasp of man had designed the universe to work according to certain “laws” then set the machine in motion.

And, as I have suggested, the language used to describe the State also became “mechanistic” by the early 1700s (see notes on week 1 and week 2 lectures).

In addition to a new metaphor, the new natural philosophers also had in common a new kind of scientific community.  Scientists who worked in Universities as well as non-university researchers now shared their discoveries through the meetings and publications of various “scientific academies,” like the Royal Society in England created in the 1660s, the French Royal Academy of Sciences formed a few years later, and then similar societies in Prussia, in northern Italy, and in Russia (Peter the Great’s Russian Imperial Academy of Sciences was founded in 1725). 

These academies had several important functions that changed the nature of science. 

    First, they established a strong link between the State and new science, since the State was often the sponsor of their research activities and publications.  (In a sense, they were early examples of the modern research “think tank.”)

     Second, they provided a new process for judging the quality of research—scientists who presented their research to the academies for discussion and publication had to produce their “proof”—their evidence and their calculations—which would be reviewed by other experts on the topic.  This is the way that modern scholarship is evaluated.

     Third, their publications and meetings became venues for the popularization of scientific discoveries to a broader audience.

     And finally, they created interlocking “communities” of scientists, who shared discoveries across national borders (which is crucial if science is going to thrive).

 

In some regards these scientific societies were the grandfathers of the “Salons” of the 1700s, the gathering places where educated people met to discuss the ideas of the Enlightenment—certainly the communities of scientists can be seen as part of the expanding “public sphere” of the early modern era.

 Putting all the bits of the New Science together—Newton

Coffin’s excellent summary of the life and work of Isaac Newton explains that Newton fused the Empiricists concern for observation and experimentation with the Cartesian’s mastery of pure mathematics.  Perhaps the best example of Newton’s method of using reason and mathematics to explain the laws that govern observed phenomenon was his invention of Calculus, so that he would have a form of mathematics that allowed him to work on the problem of explaining the planets’ irregular elliptical orbits (his results finally killed off any idea that the Earth was the center of the universe). 

That’s right—you have Isaac Newton to blame for your Calculus homework.

Newton, as you have read, published crucial research on topics ranging from Optics to Astronomy.  (And spent most of his time studying topics that we now consider un-scientific, like alchemy and theology.)

But his most important “discoveries” concerned the laws that govern motion and gravity.

Newton’s three laws regarding motion are fundamental to the way that we understand the physical world:

1)      Inertia:  a body at rest will remain at rest unless acted upon by a force; a body in rectilinear motion will remain in motion along the same path and a the same velocity unless acted upon by a force.

2)      A given force produces a measurable change in a body’s velocity, and any change in a body’s velocity is proportional to the force acting upon it.

3)      For every action or force there is an equal and opposite reaction or force.

These three laws, Newton argued, explain how gravity works—every particle of mater in the universe, regardless of how small or large exerts an attractive force on every other particle in the universe.  The strength of that force is inverse to (increases or decrease based upon) the square of the distance between the two particle (the distance multiplied by itself), and proportional to their masses. 

(Here is an example:  Jupiter has a much greater mass than the Earth, and therefor has much “greater” gravitational pull.  But because our Moon is so close to the Earth and so far from Jupiter, the force on the Moon of Earth’s gravity is greater than is the force of Jupiter’s gravity.  That’s why our mood orbits the Earth, and does not orbit Jupiter....)

Newton argued—and provided both mathematical and observational proof—that these laws applied to everything in the universe.  Why does an apple that fall to the ground?

Gravity means that the apple, which has a small mass, is pulled toward the earth, which has a large mass [the earth is pulled to the apple, too, but because of the proportions of the two masses, the pull exerted by the apple is so small as to be un-noticed].  Why do the Earth and other planets orbit the Sun?  Because of gravity. 

Again, Newton’s universe was a giant complex machine with all of the components working according to the same laws of motion and gravity, which could be explained by mathematics.

Conclusions: 

New thinking about science had dramatic applications and implications that helped change European (and world) life.

Perhaps the most obvious implications were “practical”—the new science gave humans new tools for understanding how nature works and for creating technologies that allow us to alter or control nature.  As Coffin points out, Newton’s laws helped engineers design machines (bridges, buildings, etc.), helped predict tides, draw maps, etc.

But there is another, less obvious impact:  it introduced a method of solving problems that has changed the way that we think about society as well as nature.  The new scientific method combined the collection of evidence with the application of reason to solve problems—you collect data, propose an argument that explains that data, construct a mathematical or logical proof of that argument and expose the explanation to experimental tests for verification.  A successful theory (scientists call them Laws) will allow you to predict how a phenomenon will behave.  

From this Scientific Revolution—this revolution in thinking—it was not such a great leap to wondering—can we establish the laws that govern how human societies behave (can we understand social sciences), and if we can reveal these laws, can we then use them to make human life better?  This was the question posed by the Enlightenment.

 

PART TWO:  The Enlightenment

 

In the 1700s, many (but not all!) of Europe’s philosophers, scholars, and social thinkers, were strongly influenced by a body of ideas that people at the time and since have described as “the Enlightenment.”

What Enlightenment thinkers had in common was that they (like Descartes) believed in “systematic doubt”—that everything must be subjected to the critical light of reason, and that no ideas or opinions or traditions should be accepted without first proving their accuracy and worth.

Most Enlightenment thinkers saw themselves as rejecting the “medieval” view of the world:  they believed that reason was the path to Truth, which could not be reached by  theology (or divine revelation, or the guidance of priests). 

They also rejected the Christian view that people were inherently depraved.  Humans have reason, they argued, and human behavior follows laws just as nature follows laws. 

CONTINUED NEXT WEEK

back to syllabus